The
main question at play with this week’s reading is that of children’s ability to
compute scalar implicatures. These scalar implicatures result when someone
hears a word and is able to eliminate other words that could fit in that
context because of the word that is used. For instance, the distinction between
some and all is one of the main examples examined in the reading. Barner
posits that children don’t recognize that the word some implies that something is missing. In one example, all of the
people are doing something, Children are likely to say that some people applies as well as all people to describe the situation.
Both Barner and Stiller claim that
real-world knowledge affects a person’s ability to form these scalar implicatures.
Barner finds that children fail to access scalar alternatives, or the other
possible word choices, but they do have a general ability to think
pragmatically. Thus, children must perform additional learning to access
lexical items such as these scalar alternatives. Stiller also posits a similar
reason. Children, as evidenced in his study, are able to understand ad-hoc
scales, or scales that arise from real-world context. Thus, knowledge of the
world, the language, and other people allows us to make pragmatic computations.
Children simply do not have enough of this experience to effectively do this.
To me, this raises an interesting
question. How do we acquire this ability to compute scalar implicatures as we
get older? Both Barner and Stiller suggest that children think logically, while
adults think pragmatically, when processing language. An adult, through the
experiences she has with the world and with her language, determines the
difference between some and all. The adult can recognize that a
speaker would specify all if
everything described was involved. On the other hand, some specifies a distinct lack of all. Pragmatic inference allows the adult to understand this
difference where children fail.
Yet children can understand and make
inferences in certain situations. Barner introduces the example of learning
numeric values. A child is shown two pictures, one containing one balloon and
the other containing five, with the numbers written below. The child can infer,
with his knowledge of one, that the word five must refer to the new quantity of
balloons. Thus, children already have a basis for making inferences, but only
when these inferences do not involve necessary real-world knowledge and
experience.
For me, the question of how we
acquire this ability is especially interesting considering the diversity of
human experience. Each adult takes a different path on the way to maturity and
language acquisition. No person has the same experiences. Yet all adults
arrive at the ability to compute these pragmatic implicatures. This suggests to
me that language is a unifying force in our world. Although we may all live
differently, we all eventually understand the subconscious context needed to
make these implicatures. We start off as different, but language moves us
closer together. As we interact with each other, we inform each other about
aspects of the language and the world. This creates a richer lexicon and
understanding for all. Sometimes, language seems divisive, because of its
variance and vastness. No one speaks in exactly the same way. Yet, for me, it
is a powerful idea that underneath all of this is a similar basis of real-world
knowledge and context that drives our understanding.
No comments:
Post a Comment